The Testing of Assertions
Hardly anyone is going to openly defend muddled thinking or disrespect for evidence. Rather, what people do is to surround these practices with a fog of verbiage designed to conceal from their listeners – and in most cases, I would imagine, from themselves as well – the true implications of their way of thinking. George Orwell got it right when he observed that the main advantage of speaking and writing clearly is that “when you make a stupid remark its stupidity will be obvious, even to yourself.”
Further to this, this, this and any number of things in the archive, the following may be of interest. Here’s Alan Sokal, speaking in Stockholm, May 2009, on the scientific worldview – and its opponents. Targets include practitioners of pseudo-medicine, theologians and the priestly caste of postmodernist bamboozlers. It’s a long speech and Sokal’s own leftist reflexes intrude a little too often, especially towards the end, but there are nuggets to be had. There’s an amusing schtick involving the substitution of theological fuzzwords with something more direct, and this, on religious truth claims:
Each religion makes scores of purportedly factual assertions about everything from the creation of the universe to the afterlife. But on what grounds can believers presume to know that these assertions are true? The reasons they give are various, but they ultimately boil down to one: because our holy scriptures say so. But how, then, do we know that our holy scriptures are free from error? Because the scriptures themselves say so. Now, theologians specialise in weaving elaborate webs of verbiage to avoid saying anything quite so bluntly, but this gem of circular reasoning really is the epistemological bottom line on which all “faith” is grounded. In the words of Pope John Paul II: “By the authority of His absolute transcendence, God who makes Himself known is also the source of the credibility of what He reveals.” It goes without saying that this begs the question of whether the texts at issue really were authored or inspired by God, and on what grounds one knows this. “Faith” is not in fact a rejection of reason, but simply a lazy acceptance of bad reasons. “Faith” is the pseudo-justification that some people trot out when they want to make claims without the necessary evidence.
Via James S.
Pete,
“At the risk of sounding like a broken record, do you think there is an objective moral order, and if so isn’t that taken on faith?”
I’m not sure what you mean by an “objective moral order.” I don’t think of it in quite those terms. (If a thing is objective – i.e. demonstrable and inarguable – why would it have to be “taken on faith”?) While there are common moral concerns throughout human history – punishment of wrongdoing, etc – there have been numerous conflicting imperatives and definitions of wrongdoing, depending on when and where one happened to be. What was deemed the “objective moral order” three centuries ago might be somewhat at odds with modern sensibilities. (I scarcely need to point out that slavery and human sacrifice have at times been licensed by what was regarded as an “objective moral order” and claims to know the preferences of various hypothetical deities.)
One might find something revolting and obscene in a direct and vivid way without reference to some cosmic standard of measurement. And one needn’t appeal to a cosmic standard of measurement to argue that a modern sensibility is preferable to one in which slavery or human sacrifice is part of the moral currency.
Hi David
Sorry for such a brief response, but am very busy right now.
Are you saying that slavery was moral during the era of the slave triangle? Were the abolitionists morally wrong to oppose slavery, right up until the law changed at which point they became morally correct? See, I believe it was always morally wrong, no matter if it was recognised as such at the time.
Just to pick up on your other point; Something which is objectively true is not necessarily demonstrable or inarguable. If I am right about the existence of God, then His existence is an objective fact. It does not become subjective just because I can’t prove it, or because there is room for others to disagree with me. And the same holds true for his non-existence if I am wrong.
Pete,
“Were the abolitionists morally wrong to oppose slavery, right up until the law changed at which point they became morally correct?”
That’s not what I’m saying. I’m merely pointing out that appealing to some “objective moral order” – generally God’s moral order, as variously conceived – has been done throughout history and with conflicting assumptions. Obviously, many of those appeals aren’t terribly convincing to later generations, with very good reasons. But those reasons can be arrived at, and defended, without involving God or what one thinks His preferences might be.
I’m happy to leave God out of the picture seeing as you don’t believe in Him, therefore won’t be convinced by reference to him. However, it is possible to conceive of an objective moral order without conflating it with God.
To take the sort of stance you want to take does require reference to such an objective moral standard, else what one is left with is the enforcement of personal preference. There is no reason why your preference for respecting others should take precedence over the barbarian preference for beating women.
Pete,
Sorry for the delay; was running errands.
“To take the sort of stance you want to take does require reference to such an objective moral standard, else what one is left with is the enforcement of personal preference. There is no reason why your preference for respecting others should take precedence over the barbarian preference for beating women.”
But is it an all-or-nothing situation? Conceding an epistemological point – that our knowledge is conditional (and that morality may be modified by subsequent knowledge and future possibilities) – doesn’t imply that all things are somehow equal or that no judgement can be made as to whether one view is better than another. A superior morality isn’t necessarily based on absolutes, or on intimate familiarity with the preferences of hypothetical deities.
For one thing, there’s the issue of empathy. I wouldn’t wish to be a slave or treated shabbily. Nor do I particularly enjoy treating others shabbily or as slaves. That’s just how I am, at least on a good day. I assume other people have broadly similar preferences… and hence reciprocation is possible – and positive feedback. Inferior moral systems generally involve a much greater degree of coercion and disregard for the individual. Now my knowledge of how other people think may be conditional and (to say the least) incomplete, but a workable judgement is still possible and can lead to mutual benefit.
You may choose to extend this with reference to absolutes or the alleged preferences of some hypothetical deity who happens to think much as you do; but I don’t see that as necessary. If such a belief helps you treat people well, especially in adversity, then good for you. But I find my own agnostic outlook works adequately and with fewer epistemological issues.
Update:
I don’t want to pursue this too far – we’ve already roamed from the ostensible topic – but it seems to me individuality and reciprocation are the keys to determining which morality is superior to another – in mortal terms, if not cosmic ones. As I said, inferior moral systems tend to disregard the individual and his territory, whether physical or psychological, and they also tend to rely heavily on fear, infantilism and coercion. In short, they tend to be tribal. The individual is grossly subservient to the state or collective. (I doubt anyone here would have much trouble determining why, say, the North Korean social model is indecent and disabling.)
Now one might say, “Okay, but personal preference aside, what’s so great about individualism and reciprocation?” In which case, I’d argue that societies and moral systems that favour individualism (or at least make it possible) tend to be more successful, more prosperous, more inventive, artistically and intellectually richer, etc. I don’t know if those things qualify as an “objective moral order” but they work for me. And I suspect I’m not alone in that.
david
Like I said above, “an assumed objective moral order…. is something we all take on faith, even whilst insisting that morality is subjective and relative.”
I hear your denial of an objective standard or of absolutes, yet I also hear you talking about ‘superior’ or ‘inferior’ moralities. I genuinely do not see how you can have one without the other. I don’t take issue with your agnostic outlook, but the same epistemological issues are still there only you aren’t acknowledging them.
I don’t think we’ve strayed, I’m still testing some assertions.
Pete,
I’m not sure what you mean by this:
“However, it is possible to conceive of an objective moral order without conflating it with God.”
Given what had gone before, I assumed you meant some “objective moral order” external to human preference or estimation, i.e. something absolute. Hence the God business and the epistemic problems that entails. (If a person claims to know that God exists and what He prefers, how do they know this? How do they know they know it? And so forth.) So, what “objective moral order” do you have in mind, if not something involving a deity?
“I genuinely do not see how you can have one without the other.”
Well, there’s a difference between objectively better and absolute. The criteria I suggested – prosperity, autonomy, intellectual richness, etc – are measurable and demonstrable, and so objective in a practical, everyday sense. Though I suppose some might still dispute whether they constitute an “objective moral order,” insofar as they operate in mortal terms and with a basic presumption that, broadly speaking, human misery is best reduced rather than, say, exacerbated. (I’m assuming we don’t have to ponder metaphysics in which the perpetuation of human suffering is actually desirable.) And if the factors mentioned above are acceptable as an objective standard, it’s also worth noting that people who are free to move tend to relocate their families to societies like our own. I’m not aware of any mass rush to relocate to North Korea, for instance.
“I don’t take issue with your agnostic outlook, but the same epistemological issues are still there only you aren’t acknowledging them.”
Which epistemological issues? I don’t claim to know the alleged preferences of a hypothetical deity. Compared to those who do, my estimation of why this thing is better than that seems fairly straightforward… and positively modest.
Hi David
“what “objective moral order” do you have in mind, if not something involving a deity”
You tell me! You’re the one who wants me to accept your moral precepts *as if* they have an objective basis, but without the confidence to claim as much. It seems that you think doing so leads inevitably to the acceptance of ‘a hypothetical deity’, or God, as we like to call Him. Perhaps it does, but I’m not convinced all ethicists with a belief in objective truth are theists. I suspect a peek at the philosophy books would bear this out. Perhaps some of your well-read and highly intelligent readership could confirm or deny this.
Pete,
“You tell me! You’re the one who wants me to accept your moral precepts *as if* they have an objective basis, but without the confidence to claim as much.”
I think we’re talking at cross purposes. You asked how one might argue a preference for one moral system over another without reference to some “objective moral order” – a term that still remains somewhat loaded and ambiguous. I’ve given some criteria one might use, at least as a starting point. Either you accept the criteria as objective, measurable and legitimate or you don’t, but it isn’t simply a matter of arbitrarily asserting personal preferences.
Whether the criteria I listed are objective in some cosmic sense – i.e. “rooted in something sublime and ineffable” – which is what I took you to imply – is another matter. As I said earlier, perhaps they are. It’s certainly true that moral systems tend to include unanalysed inclinations or preferences that aren’t adequately rendered in rational and quantifiable terms. That’s the nature of the beast, isn’t it? If you pursue pretty much any line of thought, sooner or later you arrive at uncertainty. (You could, I suppose, make some larger point about uncertainty, but I don’t see how that would bolster religious belief. Though I can see how it might lead to agnosticism or a profound scepticism.)
“It seems that you think doing so leads inevitably to the acceptance of ‘a hypothetical deity’, or God, as we like to call Him.”
Well, I don’t know that it leads inevitably to such things, though it often does. I’m just not sure how one might evaluate moral issues in terms of the “sublime and ineffable.” If you do that, you’re welcome to explain how.
The term ‘objective moral order’ is certainly loaded, that’s why I chose it. The term asserts the existence of truth, and that truth has a bearing on the field of morality (i.e. we can say objective/true things about human nature).
I don’t think we’re talking at cross purposes, I don’t think I have made my point clearly enough: I acknowledge happiness vs misery might plausibly be measured by objective means. That is not the issue.
The issue is that you assert that reciprocity, or ‘do unto others’, is the better way to behave. One’s own short-term and long-term interests can often be furthered by ignoring this awkward commandment, so a rational assessment of pros and cons alone does not account for why we try to treat eachother well. (If it did, we would not admire sacrafice for the sake of doing the right thing nearly so much as we do). Equally, empiricism cannot support this commandment over the commandment to kill the infidel or stone adulteresses. Behind ANY discussion of morality is the assertion that it is good to be good. I call this ineffable because it is difficult, perhaps impossible, to put into words why we ought to be good. It is something we feel or intuit rather than rationally account for. The leap involved in affirming goodness is irrational (i mean beyond reason rather than against it). You seem to be unaware that you are making such a leap!
Pete,
“Behind ANY discussion of morality is the assertion that it is good to be good. I call this ineffable because it is difficult, perhaps impossible, to put into words why we ought to be good. It is something we feel or intuit rather than rationally account for.”
Ah, that is clearer and I don’t think we disagree on the existence of non-reasoned aspects of morality. (The provenance of such things is perhaps another matter.) Certainly, there can be a drama and poignancy to morality that isn’t readily explicable in rational terms. Though, in fairness, I don’t recall suggesting otherwise.
I suspect that insofar as people try to fathom their moral assumptions at all, they often rationalise those assumptions after-the-fact, or opportunistically, or in ways that aren’t entirely consistent. I’ve suggested some rational criteria one *might* use and some practical advantages of behaving in a certain way, but that doesn’t mean I assume people think like that as a matter of course. As I said, “It’s certainly true that moral systems tend to include unanalysed inclinations or preferences that aren’t adequately rendered in rational and quantifiable terms.”
That said, it seems to me that a preference for reciprocity, autonomy, curiosity, intellectual richness, trust, etc isn’t without some fairly obvious practical advantages, both for oneself and the wider society. (For instance, courtesy is both a social lubricant and a useful personal discipline – one that encourages clarity in emotionally stressful situations. In that sense, one might even think of courtesy as a basically selfish activity that happens to have social benefits.) And cultures that favour such things, or make them possible, tend to flourish more than those that don’t. Whether or not these advantages are explicitly understood or used as moral arguments, they may be grasped instinctively and acted upon (at least some of the time).
Hi David
We’ve possibly done this topic to death, but I’m glad I made my point clear!
On the point of reciprocity and altruism being basically selfish, this doesn’t explain the acts of such figures as Maximillian Kolbe, who put himself forward for execution in order for a fellow death camp inmate to be spared. That kind of moral steadfastness is much more profound than a purely practical self-interest!
Pete,
“On the point of reciprocity and altruism being basically selfish, this doesn’t explain the acts of such figures as Maximillian Kolbe, who put himself forward for execution in order for a fellow death camp inmate to be spared. That kind of moral steadfastness is much more profound than a purely practical self-interest!”
I wasn’t suggesting pragmatism or self-interest as a sole or comprehensive explanation. I wasn’t arguing that all moral behaviour can be configured in self-serving or practical terms. I’m not making that kind of claim. There will always be self-sacrificial examples that are striking and/or symbolic. But one can, I think, argue that a great deal of moral behaviour – certainly a lot of the more prosaic aspects, civility, trust, reciprocation, etc – persist because, more often than not, they work. They often bring advantages, at least in the broader term. (One might suppose that early in human history tribes that cooperated internally had tactical advantages over tribes that didn’t organise in this way.) Again, I’m not trying to offer a comprehensive explanation; I’m just noting the existence of some practical benefits.
“We’ve possibly done this topic to death…”
Yes, possibly, at least for now. It was fun, though.
David:
Check out my book on “The Scientific Worldview. (www.scientificworldview.com)” It seems that we are on the same page.
Glenn